Available Formats
Hardback
Published: 27th January 2011
Hardback
Published: 24th February 2011
Hardback
Published: 1st November 2011
Paperback
Published: 26th March 2014
Paperback
Published: 26th March 2014
Paperback
Published: 26th March 2014
Paperback
Published: 26th March 2014
Paperback
Published: 26th March 2014
Paperback
Published: 26th March 2014
Paperback
Published: 26th March 2014
Paperback
Published: 26th March 2014
Paperback
Published: 26th March 2014
Paperback
Published: 26th March 2014
Simplicius: On Aristotle On the Heavens 1.1-4
By (Author) Simplicius
Translated by Jim Hankinson
Bloomsbury Publishing PLC
Bloomsbury Academic
26th March 2014
United Kingdom
Tertiary Education
Non Fiction
Theoretical and mathematical astronomy
185
Paperback
240
Width 156mm, Height 234mm
259g
In chapter 1 of On the Heavens Aristotle defines body, and then notoriously ruptures dynamics by introducing a fifth element, beyond Plato's four, to explain the rotation of the heavens, which, like nearly all Greeks, Aristotle took to be real, not apparent. Even a member of his school, Xenarchus, we are told, rejected his fifth element. The Neoplatonist Simplicius seeks to harmonise Plato and Aristotle. Plato, he says, thought that the heavens were composed of all four elements but with the purest kind of fire, namely light, predominating. That Plato would not mind this being called a fifth element is shown by his associating with the heavens the fifth of the five convex regular solids recognised by geometry. Simplicius follows Aristotle's view that one of the lower elements, fire, also rotates, as shown by the behaviour of comets. But such motion, though natural for the fifth elements, is super-natural for fire. Simplicius reveals that the Aristotelian Alexander of Aphrodisias recognised the need to supplement Aristotle and account for the annual approach and retreat of planets by means of Ptolemy's epicycles or eccentrics. Aristotle's philosopher-god is turned by Simplicius, following his teacher Ammonius, into a creator-god, like Plato's. But the creation is beginningless, as shown by the argument that, if you try to imagine a time when it began, you cannot answer the question, 'Why not sooner' In explaining the creation, Simplicius follows the Neoplatonist expansion of Aristotle's four 'causes' to six. The final result gives us a cosmology very considerably removed from Aristotle's.
R. J. Hankinson is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Texas at Austin.